Mary’s unique role and why Catholics and Orthodox venerate her

By: Kyle Alander

The quest to union with God is celebrated as “theosis” in Eastern Orthodox Christianity and “deification” in Roman Catholicism.  To illuminate this mystical process and address the often-misunderstood reverence for Mary within Catholic and Orthodox traditions, we turn to a compelling allegory drawn from “The Legend of Korra.” In this narrative, the fusion of Wan, a mortal, with Raava, a divine spirit, mirrors the transformative journey towards divinity and sheds light on Mary’s unique veneration. This analogy not only elucidates the potential for human transcendence but also aims to bridge understanding, particularly among Protestants, regarding the high regard in which Mary is held. Through this exploration, we delve into the nuances of spiritual growth in Christian theology and the special status of Mary, hoping to clarify her role and veneration using a relatable and enlightening allegory.

The Fusion of Wan and Raava: A Symbol of Transformation



In “The Legend of Korra,” the story of Wan and Raava presents a vivid illustration of the transformative potential inherent in union with the divine. Wan, a mere mortal, embarks on a journey of growth and discovery that leads him to a pivotal moment of fusion with Raava, a spirit of light and peace. This union transcends Wan’s human limitations, endowing him with remarkable abilities and the responsibility of being the Avatar, a bridge between the human and spiritual realms.

Parallels with Theosis and Deification:

This narrative mirrors the spiritual journey of theosis or deification, where the believer, through grace, virtue, and the sacraments, enters into a closer union with the Divine. Just as Wan’s fusion with Raava does not erase his humanity but elevates it, theosis and deification do not make the believer divine in essence but sanctify their nature to reflect divine attributes more fully.

The Dynamic of Transformation:

The transformation experienced by Wan is not instantaneous but the culmination of a journey marked by trials, learning, and growth. Similarly, theosis and deification are processes of spiritual evolution, where the believer’s character and actions are progressively aligned with divine qualities such as love, wisdom, and holiness. This journey is marked by a synergetic relationship between divine grace and human effort, where each step forward is both a gift and a personal commitment to growth.

The Distinction in Union:

It’s crucial to note that while Wan becomes the Avatar, he does not become Raava in essence, nor does Raava lose her distinct identity or become Wans essence. This distinction parallels the theological nuance in theosis and deification, where the believer partakes in the divine nature without becoming God in essence. The union enhances and transforms the believer’s capabilities and understanding, much like Wan’s abilities are expanded, yet the fundamental distinction between the Creator and the creation is maintained.

The analogy of Wan’s fusion with Raava from “The Legend of Korra” offers an understandable narrative to understand the complex and mystical journey of becoming more like the Divine as outlined in Christian theology. It highlights the transformative potential of divine-human union, the gradual nature of spiritual growth, and the maintenance of essential distinctions, providing a captivating entry point into the exploration of theosis and deification.

Mary’s Unique Journey and Veneration Distinctions

Building on the analogy from “The Legend of Korra,” where Wan’s transformation through fusion with Raava symbolizes the spiritual journey towards theosis or deification, we can further explore this transformative theme by applying it to the unique status and veneration of Mary in Christian tradition. Mary’s role as the Theotokos, or God-bearer, presents a singular example of divine-human cooperation and highlights the nuances of veneration within the Christian faith.

Mary: The Ultimate Model of Union:

In Christian theology, Mary represents the epitome of synergy between human willingness and divine grace. Her fiat, or “yes” to God’s plan, marks the beginning of a profound union with the divine, culminating in the Incarnation. Analogous to Raava’s choice to fuse with Wan, Mary’s acceptance brings about a unique intersection of the human and divine. However, unlike the fusion that creates the Avatar, Mary’s union with the divine does not endow her with divine essence but makes her the vessel through which God enters the world in human form.

Distinctions in Veneration: Understanding Mary’s Place

The reverence for Mary within Christianity, especially in Catholic and Orthodox traditions, is deeply rooted in her unique role in salvation history. Drawing from the earlier analogy, just as Wan’s transformation and new role are recognized and respected, Mary is honored in a special way, reflected in the concept of hyperdulia. This level of veneration is distinct from latria, the worship due to God alone, and dulia, the reverence given to saints and holy figures.

– Hyperdulia: Reserved solely for Mary, hyperdulia acknowledges her unparalleled cooperation with divine grace and her role as the Mother of God. This form of veneration is akin to recognizing Wan’s unique status as the Avatar, though the analogy falls short of fully encapsulating Mary’s singular position in Christian devotion.

– Dulia: The respect and honor given to the saints, akin to how other significant but not Avatar-level figures in “The Legend of Korra” might be esteemed. These figures are celebrated for their virtues and deeds, serving as models of faith.

– Latria: This is the worship that is directed exclusively towards God, paralleled by the ultimate reverence shown to the spirit of Raava before her fusion with Wan. Despite Wan’s elevated status post-fusion, the reverence due to Raava (representing the divine) remains of a fundamentally different order.

Mary’s Transformative Example:

Mary’s journey reflects the highest potential for human cooperation with divine grace, embodying the profound potential within each believer to respond to God’s call with faith and humility. Her “yes” to God, though simple, reverberates through time as the ultimate act of human participation in God’s salvific plan. This act of consent did not elevate Mary to a divine status but positioned her as a pivotal figure in the history of salvation, through which the divine and human natures were united in the person of Jesus Christ.

Mary’s unique role and the subsequent veneration she receives underscore the multifaceted nature of Christian piety. Her journey exemplifies the pinnacle of human cooperation with divine will, making her an unparalleled figure of reverence within the Christian tradition. The special veneration of hyperdulia accorded to Mary does not detract from the worship due to God (latria) but enriches the tapestry of Christian devotion by highlighting the role of human willingness in the divine plan.

The Role of Mary as a Model for Believers:

In the same way that Wan’s story in “The Legend of Korra” serves as a narrative of transformation and responsibility, Mary’s story inspires believers to open their hearts to God’s grace. She exemplifies the transformative power of divine grace when met with human openness and consent. Mary’s journey invites believers to contemplate their own capacity for cooperation with God’s grace and to aspire towards such a profound union with the divine will.

The distinctions of dulia, hyperdulia, and latria within Christian veneration serve not only as theological categories but as expressions of the manifold ways divine grace operates within creation. Mary, through her unique role and the exceptional veneration she receives, stands as a testament to the extraordinary works of grace in human history. Her elevation through hyperdulia reflects the awe and reverence inspired by God’s action in her life, an action that remains unparalleled but invites emulation in its openness to divine will.

The Harmony of Divine Grace and Human Response:

The journey of Mary, from her fiat to her unique role in salvation history, encapsulates the beautiful synergy between divine grace and human cooperation. The analogy of Wan and Raava, drawn from “The Legend of Korra,” while a narrative from a different context, serves to illustrate this profound relationship in an accessible and engaging manner. Through this lens, we see the transformative potential that lies in the union between the divine and the human, a theme central to both the animated series and Christian theology.

Mary’s response to God’s call, characterized by humility and profound faith, sets a precedent for believers. It demonstrates that divine grace, when met with a willing human heart, can bring about extraordinary outcomes in the fabric of salvation history. This dynamic interplay between divine initiative and human cooperation is a cornerstone of Christian understanding of sanctity and the journey towards holiness.

In venerating Mary, Christians do not merely honor a historical figure but recognize and celebrate the transformative power of divine grace manifested in human life. The veneration accorded to Mary, especially in the form of hyperdulia, goes beyond mere admiration. It is a recognition of her unique cooperation with God’s grace, making her a model for all who seek to respond to God’s call with a willing and open heart.

Furthermore, this veneration serves as a reminder of the dignity and potential of every human being to partake in God’s salvific plan. Just as Mary played a pivotal role in the Incarnation, each believer is called to participate in the ongoing story of salvation through their lives and actions, inspired by her example.

The harmony of divine grace and human response, exemplified in Mary’s life, invites a deeper reflection on the nature of sanctity and the call to holiness that lies at the heart of Christian life. It challenges believers to consider their own openness to God’s grace and their willingness to cooperate with divine will, aspiring to reflect the divine in their own lives.

In conclusion, the journey of Mary, illuminated through the distinctions of veneration within Christian tradition, offers a rich tapestry of themes for contemplation. Her story, marked by a profound union with the divine, exemplifies the potential for human beings to transcend their limitations through cooperation with divine grace. This narrative, rooted in the Christian faith and paralleled in the transformative journey of Wan and Raava, invites believers to a deeper engagement with the divine mystery, encouraging a life of faith, humility, and active participation in God’s redemptive work in the world.

A Critique of Descartes Introspectionism & Epistemological Infallibalism

Note: This essay was originally written for my Philosophy of Mind course. In my research in formal epistemology I have accepted a form of epistemic falliblism which is termed “radical probabilism” in the literature.

One argument against this form of fallibilism is from Descartes argument on the infallibility of the cogito ergo sum. In this paper I challenge his argument in detail

By: Kyle Alander

Rene Descartes argues we have infallible knowledge of our mental states, his argument is based on the infallibility of cogito ergo sum (I Think, Therefore, I Am), this is known as introspectionism. However, introspectionism has been recently challenged by Nisbett, De Camp Wilson & Schwitzgebel. They argue through a set of experiments that introspection is unreliable and so fallible, their position is anti-introspectionism. I will reinforce their conclusions by adding an additional problem for Descartes’ position. Descartes’ account of the infallibility of cogito ergo sum relies on two background assumptions, the first assumption is us having infallible knowledge about logic, and the second assumption is a specific account of incorrigible doubt. I will argue that on philosophical grounds these two assumptions are wrong and so it would lead to a fallibilism about the contents of our minds making at least some form of anti-introspectionism as true.


Exposition:

Descartes’s introspectionism says that we can have infallible knowledge of our mental states. This mental infallibility entails that we cannot be mistaken about our mental states, the mental states include our beliefs, reasons, and other mental stuff in our minds. He also believes that he has special introspective access to his mental states. His main argument is that an evil demon can deceive him about his external world sense perceptions but cannot deceive him about his mental thinking, this is from his famous “I Think, Therefore, I Am” statement.


Nisbett and De Camp Wilson disagree with Descartes and so hold to anti-introspectionism, their thesis is based on a set of experiments that show that people cannot accurately report on what is the mental stuff in their minds, rather when people report they are reliant on a priori theory about what they are thinking rather than the mental items themselves. An a priori theory is a theory or narrative that is in your head regarding your identity and mental contents. So we can only report accurately when we have a theory about our mind and its contents rather than the mind and contents of the mind itself. For example, when the subjects are asked to write speeches that go against their own views they will later adopt the contrary view and then revise the history of their beliefs to state that they believed the contrary view the whole time. So this would be an example of people reporting not on what is actually in their minds but what they theorized was in their mind


Schwitzgebel adopts another form of anti-introspectionism, he claims that while introspection is very important to our everyday life it is unreliable in telling us what is going on inside our heads. He bases this on the notion that we can ask questions about the contents of our mind and not be certain about it. He uses the example of our emotions and sensory experiences and how we can misjudge these mental states. Like when we feel joy or anger these can often be conflated, and we often don’t understand why we are joyful or angry much of the time. So the very fact that we can question our own emotions of introspection is evidence for a kind of anti-introspectionism.

Critical Evaluation:

I will argue that on philosophical grounds that we do not have infallible knowledge about logic and that Descartes specific account of incorrigible doubt is wrong. If either of my arguments succeeds then it would lead to a fallibilism about the contents of our minds making at least some form of anti-introspectionism as true.


First, we can deny the underlying logic of Descartes’s argument by the following thought experiment: the evil demon can deceive us about modus ponens. Modus ponens is the logical statement: if P then Q, P, Therefore Q. It could be the case that we are simply wrong about modus ponens because anytime we do the logic the demon steps in to make us have a false belief. However for the cogito ergo sum to work we must assume that modus ponens works and not be possibly wrong about it.


An objection defending Descartes is that even an omnipotent demon cannot change logic and so cannot deceive us about it. However this misses the point of the problem since I am not making an ontological claim about the ability of a demon to change logic, I can grant that it cannot do that. Instead, I am making an epistemological claim: we could be deceived about our understanding or knowledge of logic. So my objection to Descartes does not rest on the ability of the demon to change logic it only rests on the ability of the demon to mess with our knowledge about logic.  Thus Descartes’s demon could deceive us about the very foundations of logic, making us doubt the logic behind the cogito ergo sum.


Second, we can question Descartes account of incorrigible doubts. Consider this thought experiment: let’s say that I am sitting on my armchair, engaging in philosophical thought. I experience sensation Z containing the thought “I am doubting”, and then there is sensation Y which contains the thought “I am hungry”. So when I experience Z I form the belief “I am doubting”, but then one day I get sensation Z and form the belief “I am hungry” or more critically I form the sensation Y (something that is supposed to be my hunger) and form the belief “I am doubting”. We are left with a problem, I was mistaken in that instance since the sensation Y contains something incorrect.


An objection to this thought experiment is that even if we have a sensation Y and not Z, we are still in fact doubting since doubting implies thinking and so we can still have infallible knowledge about thinking and doubting.


However, this objection doesn’t work. The challenge for the cartesian is how we get to the knowing we are thinking and doubting. We can’t know we are thinking and doubting based on something false as knowledge requires we had the correct chain of justification all along, it is not merely about getting to the truth. Another way to put it is that if we are in a state such that we form the belief we are doubting based on false sensations, then we cannot know we are doubting as our belief is not rightly connected to our sensation, we simply got ‘lucky’ that we got to the correct belief that we are doubting, but our justification is flawed and so isn’t sufficient for knowledge. This is a serious problem for Descartes account of incorrigible doubt since his views rely on the assumption that the justification regarding the doubt is itself through a correct chain of justification. But there is an in-principle way where we can be wrong about our sensations about our doubts. Since there is an in principle way for us to be wrong about our doubts this reinforces the conclusion that Descartes’ account of incorrigible doubts is mistaken.


These considerations make both of Descartes views wrong. I have shown that us having infallible knowledge about logic and Descartes specific account of incorrigible doubt are both mistaken. Therefore since those assumptions are false it leads to a fallibilism about the contents of our minds making at least some form of anti-introspectionism as true.

Answering a Declaration of War: A Call For an Armistice

This is a guest post by David Pallmann in response to a recent article titled ‘A Declaration of War on Young Apologetics‘. The content in this blog post is therefore representative of his views and may not necessarily be shared by all those who consider themselves to be youth apologist. To see the blog owners perspective (Kyle Alander) see this critical review

By: David Pallmann

Not long ago, an article entitled “A Declaration of War on Young Apologists” began circulating online which constituted a not-so-subtle rebuke of myself among others. The article designates these individuals as “young apologists.” The article was motivated by certain criticisms which these individuals have raised against contemporary popular Christian apologetics. The moniker “young apologist” is, of course, problematic since most young people who engage in apologetics do not typically criticize popular apologetics. I think it probably would have been better to just address me (or whoever else the authors of this article had in mind) by name. This would save us the trouble of seeking a better label for the group of individuals in question. For the sake of simplicity, I will accept the label “young apologist” throughout this article, but under duress.

I also find it unhelpful to designate this disagreement as a “war.” Ironically, as we shall see, this designation seems to make the authors of this article guilty of the very thing which they criticize the “young apologists” for doing – namely creating infighting within the apologetics community. Rather than violently fighting about our disagreements, I propose that we have a civil conversation about the disagreement.

The article was written by Chris Stockman and Will Hess and was published on Hess’ blog The Church Split which is affiliated with his podcast of the same name. One must note the irony in Hess’ involvement in and publication of this article inasmuch as one of the stated objectives of his ministry to “challenge the status quo.” That is the very thing which the “young apologists” are attempting to do with respect to popular apologetics. And yet, a running theme throughout the article is that they ought not do this! Challenging the status quo is (apparently) only okay when Hess disagrees with it. Double standards along with misunderstandings, as we shall see, are a recurring problem throughout this article.

Stockman and Hess are both friends of mine. Hess, in particular, I love like a brother. This article is written with a deep appreciation for both of them no matter how harsh it sounds at times. I want to take their concerns seriously, offer clarification where it is appropriate, and offer criticisms of their arguments and objections when necessary. My hope is that, if nothing else, this will at least bring some much-needed clarity to the disagreement even if it doesn’t resolve it. Although I am acting as a spokesperson for the diverse group of individuals who have been labeled “young apologists” I will be offering my own unique perspective. So what I say here may not always reflect the sentiments of all “young apologists” on every issue raised by the article.

Lack of Clarity

In the introductory paragraph, Stockman introduces the issue and then puts forward what I take to be the thesis statement of the article: “They [young apologists] are bright, but are doing more harm than good at the moment.” Now this is immediately an extremely vague thesis. What sort of harm? Harm to the cause of Christ? Harm to the apologetic enterprise? Harm to the fragile ego of certain popular apologists? It’s just not clear what sort of harm we are supposed to be doing. As such, it becomes difficult to see how the thesis statement is supported by the following discussion.

Stockman proceeds to explain how some of us are critical of certain popular apologetic arguments. The problems with this, according to him, are “1) some of them do this far too often, and 2) some of them, if you didn’t know them from Adam, would be confused for the village atheist with what their critiques are as well as how incessant they are.” So regarding 1, how often is too often? It’s like Stockman is okay with some criticisms of popular apologetic arguments, but not too much. So what’s the cut-off point? And how can it be justified in a non-arbitrary way? Needless to say, Stockman doesn’t tell us. Charitably he might be interpreted as saying that “young apologists” critique popular apologetics more than they build a positive case for Christianity. I would agree that, if this is what we are doing, then this is a problem since the apologist’s primary task is to defend the faith. But under this interpretation, the objection simply doesn’t apply to most of the people who Stockman clearly has in mind.

Regarding the second point, it seems to me that a degree of confusion is inevitable whenever one is criticizing common arguments used to support some position. For example, I have been accused of being a Calvinist for objecting to the use of certain arguments against Calvinism. I have been accused of being an evolutionist for objecting to the use of certain arguments for a young earth. I have been accused of being a determinist for objecting to the use of certain arguments for free will. Yet I affirm neither Calvinism, nor evolution, nor determinism.

Those who are untrained in philosophy have an unfortunate tendency to confuse the rejection of some argument for a proposition with a rejection of the proposition itself. But that is an a invalid inference, and the proper solution is to remind people that one can accept a proposition while rejecting certain arguments for it. The solution is most certainly not to avoid objecting to bad arguments lest someone make an invalid inference to the conclusion that you reject the proposition which the bad arguments are supposed to support. We simply don’t have to cater to people’s irrationality. And Stockman has given no argument to the contrary.

Double Standards

Stockman says “Here, I am not saying not to criticize wrong ideas. Of course, if an apologist like Frank Turek or Michael Licona is incorrect on something, it should be (graciously) pointed out. But, by who? Twenty-something’s with YouTube channels that nobody watches?” Observe that the grievance here is not the criticizing of poor arguments. That is explicitly said to be okay. The problem, according to Stockman, lies with who is doing the criticizing. Why are “young apologists” not supposed to be criticizing bad apologetics according to Stockman? He gives two reasons: 1) their age, and 2) the size of their following. 

Aside from being an obvious ad hominem, Stockman seems to have a double standard here. Presumably he doesn’t think that one’s age or the size of their following is relevant when it comes to pointing out the lousy arguments of the new atheists. He would be the first to call a foul if Richard Dawkins objected to someone criticizing him based upon their age or the size of their following. So why have these factors suddenly become a big deal when it comes to pointing out the lousy arguments of popular apologists? How come a twenty-something with a small YouTube channel is allowed to point out problems with Richard Dawkins but not with Frank Turek? The double standard is glaring.

Confusions

A little later in the article we get this rather odd statement: “Turek is an excellent apologist, because he is an evangelist. Not a professional philosopher, but an evangelist.” Stockman seems to have missed the fact that an apologist and an evangelist are two different things. The two vocations are compatible and mutually support one another to be sure. But they are distinct and it is possible to be good at one and terrible at the other. Ray Comfort, I think, is an example of someone who is a great evangelist and a terrible apologist. His banana argument for God’s existence is among the worst theistic arguments in history. Comfort doesn’t become a great apologist just because he is a great evangelist, and the same is true of Turek (though I should add that Turek makes a marginally better case for theism than Comfort).

Stockman further claims “Apologetics is about the gospel and equipping Christ’s church, not the academic discussions. It can involve those but it is not reducible to them. I think it a grievous mistake to reduce the Gospel of Christ to one of many items of discussion in the Philosophy of Religion arena.” But this is just clearly wrong. The defense of the Gospel is different than the proclamation of the Gospel. The two certainly work together, but they are absolutely not the same. Apologetics is pre-evangelistic and it is needed more than ever in the modern world. This is why it is so important that our pre-evangelism is done properly because that is what lays the foundation for evangelism. Stockman has, unfortunately, compressed pre-evangelism and evangelism into a single activity. To be very clear, I am not saying that one cannot be both an evangelist and an apologist, nor am I saying that the two tasks cannot be done in the same setting. I merely drawing a conceptual distinction between the two tasks to show that one cannot be reduced to or understood in terms of the other.

At one point, Hess says “These popular apologists have reached hundreds of thousands of people for the cause of Christ, seen many come to Christ, and have inspired others (like yours truly) to get in the game. Yet, these starting apologists will condescend these people (or their followers) with such an air of superiority the message falls entirely flat. What’s even more ironic is these young apologists claim to deal with “the real issues” (suggesting that those like CS Lewis never dealt with real issues), but have been unable to amass any following themselves. The ones who haven’t managed to build a following have a much smaller audience (and therefore influence) on the conversation as a whole. You wanna know why? You guessed it. Nobody cares.”

I think that I speak for all of the young apologists when I say that I am truly thankful for each and every person who has come to Christ because of Frank Turek. No one is disputing that God can work through broken instruments. That’s not the issue. The problems with popular apologetics don’t go away or become insignificant just because popular apologetics has brought many people to Christ.

As to why some of us have smaller followings, Hess claims that this is due to the fact that nobody cares. Perhaps that is true, but that just speaks badly of popular apologists. The fact that you don’t care about objections to your arguments does nothing to reduce their potency. Indeed, to the extent that one cares about popular arguments for Christianity, one might think that they should care about objections to them. Furthermore, it is unclear that our smaller followings are due to apathy as Hess suggests. We are, by definition, young apologists. We haven’t had as much time as someone like Frank Turek has had to amass a large following. Certainly the lack of a following could be due to general apathy towards what we have to say. But it is just as likely to be due to the short amount of time that we have been involved in apologetics. To decide one way or the other, at present, is just premature.

Finally, Hess overlooks the fact that our smaller followings could be due to the fact that we are attempting to soberly and seriously engage with apologetic issues. We aren’t interested in giving the superficially witty, one-line zingers to the questions which skeptics asks us. These sorts of answers are rhetorically powerful. They are great for getting views, likes, shares, and for drawing a following. But they are terrible for actually understanding and answering questions. Perhaps our followings are smaller because we aren’t primarily focused upon building them. As John Hanby correctly says, “One reason Turek or Strobel get more views than Rob Koons, for example, is because quick, witty, over-simplistic, flamboyant ~arguments get more clicks than sober, nuanced, thoughtful, logically airtight sound arguments. This is indicative of Youtube algorithms, and human nature, not indicative of the effectiveness of pop apologetics.”

Irrelevancies

At one point, Hess includes the following bizarre section within the article: ““BUT WHAT ABOUT THE GETTIER PROBLEM!?” … Nobody cares.” No one cares indeed. At least no one cares within the context of the current dispute. So why does Hess bring up such a manifestly irrelevant issue? My best guess is that this has something to do with my passing reference to the Gettier problem in my recent video critiquing Tim Stratton’s freethinking argument (of which Hess is a fan). But even then I only mentioned it briefly because it is relevant to something within Stratton’s argument where the argument touches on epistemology. And believe me, in epistemology, everyone cares about the Gettier problem.

Misunderstandings

Stockman quotes John Hanby as follows: “But there are countless examples who are less popular than Frank Turek, but are better at defending the Christian faith. Joshua Rasmussen, Rob Koons, Eleonore Stump, Alexander Pruss, Joshua Sijuwade, Andrew Loke, Timothy McGrew, and Richard Swinburne are all great places to start.” He then claims that “The claim is that you should start with these. Not gradually work your way up to, but start with.” and draws the conclusion that “All of these names are indeed great thinkers. … But they are (with the possible exception of Rasmussen) horrible places to start. … So why would it be such a bad idea to start with great thinkers? It’s simple: aside from Rasmussen, they have done (practically) nothing at a lay level … The aspiring apologist should start with what they can understand.” Hess understands our grievances in a similar way, saying “Think about it. It’s hard enough to get most Christians today onboard with popular apologetics being a regular part of their churches or conversations, and you want to bring in even more technical stuff?”

So first off, the quotation simply does not say that one must start by reading academic works or even academics. Stockman is just clearly reading more into the quotation than it says. No one is suggesting that the budding apologist should start reading literature which is above their comprehension level. Certainly if one is able to understand academic philosophy, then I think that there is no reason for them to waste their time reading popular material since they are already above that. But if someone is just starting out, our claim is not that they cannot read material on their own level. Rather, the claim is that the material which they read and adopt should be good quality material – not what Frank Turek is offering.

Stockman is correct that there is an unfortunate dearth of good quality entry-level apologetic material. But the solution is surely not to ignore the problems with the existing entry-level apologetic material! The solution is to popularize high quality Christian philosophy which is, in many ways, what we “young apologists” are wanting people like Frank Turek to do. As philosophers like Josh Rasmussen have made clear, it is indeed possible to popularize high quality theistic arguments without incurring the sorts of problems which “young apologists” are identifying in Frank Turek’s arguments. Our claim is not that beginners should begin with high level philosophy. No, our claim is that popularizers should popularize quality material.

Stockman closes this section by saying “I have to either seriously question the humility of these young so-called apologists, or else their self-awareness.” What he should be questioning instead is his reading of our statements or, more precisely, he should be questioning what he is reading into our statements. The bottom line is that no one, to my knowledge, is claiming that beginners should start by reading academic works. The claim is that the popular material is largely poor quality and so there needs to be a popularization of the high quality material. Does Stockman object to this? And if so, why?

Stockman quotes me (albeit not by name) as saying “If seasoned apologists spent more time teaching up-and-coming Christian apologists how to respond to the likes of Graham Oppy, JH Sobel, and Evan Fales, they wouldn’t ever have to bother teaching them how to respond to the likes of Dawkins, Hitchens, and Dillahunty. Showing the flaws in bottom-tier atheist objections to Christianity borders on being a waste of time.” He replies by saying “I talk with skeptics regularly (in person, which is the last thing many of Turek’s detractors do), and “the likes of Graham Oppy, JH Sobel, and Evan Fales” have been mentioned a sum total of never. So why should apologists prepare the younger generation to encounter those arguments?”

Stockman must run in different groups than me since I encounter objections based upon the work of these great atheist philosophers regularly. But in any case, that isn’t the point. The point is that that there is value in learning how to think and knowing that your beliefs can withstand even the most rigorous scrutiny. Apparently this is not all that important to Stockman. His question seems to indicate that one only need know the bare minimum to get by in the encounters which they actually face. At the risk of sounding a bit cynical, it looks like Stockman doesn’t think that knowing Christianity can stand up to even the toughest criticism is valuable for it’s own sake. All that matters is that you can say something in response to the questions you actually get asked. Who care if you have answers to serious objections as long as you never actually meet someone who raises them, right? This is not a posture that I would recommend. It encourages apologists to merely regurgitate answers rather than to be thinkers. And I think that this is the real heart of the matter. Often times, it seems that all popular apologists care about is having a pre-loaded response to objections. To the ‘young apologists’ this communicates a lack of concern for the person making the objection as well as for the subject matter. ‘Young apologists’ are more concerned with teaching people how to think than in teaching them what to think.

Stockman further says “If you are not training to answer the questions and objections you are actually going to face, then you are not training for apologetics. You may be sharpening your thinking, or testing yourself, but it is not apologetics that you are doing.” But Stockman misses the point. The point is that if you are prepared to defend Christianity at the highest levels of intellectual criticism you will, of necessity, be prepared for anything lower than that. The claim is not that one shouldn’t be prepared to answer the bottom tier objections from new atheists. The claim is that if one is prepared to answer the more serious objections, this will also equip them to answer the less serious objections. It’s not either-or. It’s both.

Here we come to, perhaps, the most egregious misunderstanding within the entire article. Stockman refers to this as the heart of the problem with “young apologists.” He again quotes only the last line of the aforementioned quotation from me, and says “Those bottom-tier objections are objections that Christians face. … So, your friend just challenged you on good people suffering. But don’t worry, the apologists are here to help! And they say…showing the flaws in that objection is a waste of time. Your older brother went off to college and heard a professor say that science has removed the need for a God, and now it’s Thanksgiving and he’s an atheist. Answering your brother? A waste of time. Your little sister is hearing at school that she shouldn’t be a Christian because it’s sexually oppressive, and that she should “experiment” and “find” herself? Answering her is a waste of time. These scenarios are all too common, and we all know that, despite these objections being low-hanging fruit, answering them means everything in the world. Why? Because it means everything to the person you are answering. If someone has not grasped the inherit relational nature of apologetics, they should stop speaking on the subject, because they do not know what they are talking about. One does not just answer an objection; they are also answering the person in an effort to till the ground for the gospel.”

I will give Stockman the benefit of the doubt that this is not a deliberate misrepresentation, but it is at the very least a serious misunderstanding. The sentence preceding the statement that “Showing the flaws in bottom-tier objections to Christianity borders on being a waste of time” contextualizes the statement. Before saying that, I had said “If seasoned apologists spent more time teaching up-and-coming Christian apologists how to respond to the likes of Graham Oppy, JH Sobel, and Evan Fales, they wouldn’t ever have to bother teaching them how to respond to the likes of Dawkins, Hitchens, and Dillahunty.” So what is the context of the statement? I am obviously talking about seasoned apologists training budding apologists. I was saying that if you taught Christian apologists how to answer academic atheists then, as a consequence of that teaching, they would then also know how to respond to the bottom-tier objections. I was saying that it is a waste of time to teach upcoming apologists how to answer the new atheists and then to teach them how to answer the philosophical atheists. Why? Because you could kill two birds with one stone as it were by just beginning with the philosophical atheists. That was my point. This should be evident from the context. Moreover Stockman knows that this is the context because he quoted it earlier.

But rather than deal with the point I was actually making, he takes the last sentence out of context and then acts as though I intended to say that under any and all circumstances, it is a waste of time to answer bottom-tier objections to Christianity. I realize that he may not have intended this. Indeed, I hope that he did not. But the fact remains that this is a gross distortion of what I actually said. Let me be very clear: there is nothing wrong with answering lousy objections to Christianity when a critic is raising them against Christianity. However, those who teach others how to do apologetics do them a great disservice if those are the only (or even the primary) kinds of objections which they teach them to anticipate. 

Now let me take this as an opportunity to turn the tables on Stockman. He seems to be saying that we should not be teaching upcoming apologists about the more serious objections to Christianity or, at least, that its not important that they know about them. The problem here is that this can have the same negative results as the ones Stockman was attempting to lecture me over. What happens when you only teach apologists how to deal with bottom-tier objections to Christianity because you (wrongly) think that these are the only objections to Christianity which they will ever encounter, and then they come across real objections from people who have actually thought about this stuff for more than 5 minutes? You’ve given them an illusion that the arguments against Christianity are much weaker than they actually are, and lured them into a false sense of intellectual security. You have set them up for failure. If, on the other hand, we teach apologists how to answer the strongest objections up-front, then they will be totally unfazed by the bottom-tier objections. There is no danger of them coming to feel like apologists tricked them into rejecting a dime-store version of atheism while never dealing with the real thing.

Still later in the article, we find Will Hess saying “I tire of young “would-be-apologists” flippantly putting down popular apologists for casting a wide net and “not going deep enough”. The reality is, their job isn’t to go deep on every topic. Their job is to present the broadest case for Christianity and address the most common objections to Christianity while inviting people to hear the gospel: to be evangelistic.” Like Stockman, Hess has misunderstood the nature of our grievances with popular apologetics. The objection is not that popular apologists “don’t go deep enough.” The objection is that their arguments are often bad. They are frequently not giving people good reasons to believe that Christianity is true, and they are not giving real answers to the arguments against Christianity. The problem is not (necessarily) their level of understanding; it is their content.

Hess also says, “These budding apologists who are upset that J Warner Wallace isn’t responding to Kant’s arguments against miracles or Oppy’s thoughts on Ontological Arguments need to have a serious reality check:” Who is upset about this? Who has made this objection? It looks very much like Hess is attacking a figment of his own imagination here. He goes on to say “Just because someone isn’t interested in a topic that only you and maybe 7 others are interested in doesn’t mean they’re all ignorant chimps.” But again, the objection isn’t that popular apologists aren’t interested in the same topics as we are. It’s that they are speaking on topics for which they have only a surface-level understanding and, consequently, are misrepresenting the issues and options to their audiences.

Hess follows this up by saying “Perhaps, they have simply done enough research in areas to answer their gnawing questions and have since moved on to raise their families, start a business, run a law firm, etc.” But the issue is that they are not merely satisfying their own intellectual curiosity and then moving on. People like Frank Turek are public figures who publicly talk about the case for Christianity. These people need to have a better understanding of the issues than what is needed to answer their own doubts for they are also supposed to be answering the doubts of others. Why is it a bad thing that we would want them to be competent to do that?

Hess also complains that “These popular apologists serve a specific role in the church: to popularize apologetics. To help people overcome the biggest objections to Christianity today and help the masses give themselves permission to believe. They serve as an entryway to the world of apologetics, philosophy, and theology. That’s their role. To expect them to be an expert on textual criticism, theological disputes, epistemology, metaphysics, and history is just wildly unrealistic.” And of course, we “young apologists” completely agree with this! Once again, we want them to popularize good arguments, not crappy arguments. No one is saying that they have to be an expert on everything. Hess is again attacking a figment of his own imagination.

So What Is The Agenda?

Hitherto I’ve pointed out that Stockman and Hess engage in quite a bit a misrepresentation. I trust that this is not deliberate on their part, and likely results from poor communication on the part of so-called “young apologists” as well as poor interpretation on the part of Stockman and Hess. So for the purposes of advancing this conversation in the right direction, let me be very clear about the motivation lying behind many of the criticisms of popular apologetics. The primary motivation is simply faithfulness to the our Lord’s command to do unto others as we would have them do unto us (Lk 6:31, Matt 7:12). Allow me to illustrate.

As someone involved in the world of Christian apologetics, I can’t tell you how many times people ask me to comment on what critics of the faith have to say. As I read their material and watch their content, one problem stands out among the others. There is a lack of familiarity with the full range of options which are open to Christians on certain issues, and there is a lack of engagement with what knowledgeable Christians have written on these subjects. When a skeptic objects that there is huge contradiction between predestination and free will or between foreknowledge and free will in Scripture, I have to roll my eyes. They are just demonstrating that they lack a mature understanding of the Christian faith, and that Christians have many viable options with respect to these issues. When a skeptic brings up the problem of the Canaanite genocide or the problem of evil, but shows no awareness of the diversity of Christian responses to these problems, I tend to stop taking them seriously because they just haven’t done their homework. I call skeptics out for this.

The issue is that the same problem is pervasive among popular Christian apologists. I can’t tell you how many times I see apologists conflating atheism with materialism or assuming that all atheists are logical positivists and moral relativists. I have to roll my eyes when Christian apologists do this because, just like skeptics who fail to understand how broad the Christian tent really is, these apologists are failing to understand how broad the atheist tent is. When an apologist says that atheists can’t account for objective morality, but shows no awareness of robust non-theistic accounts of ethics, I can’t take their claim seriously. They haven’t done their homework and they don’t know what they are talking about. So, to be consistent, I also call apologists out for doing this.

Those of us who are being called “young apologists” don’t want skeptics to attack overly narrow understandings of Christianity or to fail to proportion their confidence to their knowledge of the subject matter. In the same way, we don’t want Christian apologists to attack overly narrow understandings of atheism or to fail to proportion their confidence to their knowledge of the subject matter. This is an attempt to be consistent and to try to take atheism as seriously as we would want atheists to take Christianity. If you don’t like it when atheists attack the most cartoonish versions of Christianity, it’s probably a good idea not to attack the most cartoonish versions of atheism.

Conclusion

Not only have Stockman and Hess failed to justify their thesis that what we are doing is somehow harmful, they also seem to have missed our central concern. We aren’t claiming that nothing can be simplified for a popular audience, we aren’t claiming that budding apologists must start out by reading the works of Richard Swinburne, and we certainly aren’t claiming that it is a waste of time to answer the objections which people actually raise when they raise them. We are simply urging the apologetics community to be consistent, to treat atheism with the same level of respect as we want them to treat Christianity. This requires us, popular apologists included, at a minimum to avoid misrepresenting atheism and to avoid overstating the case for Christianity. That is the issue. If Stockman and Hess want to fight a war with us, they had better start aiming their guns at the actual points we are making instead of shooting high over our heads at claims which no one has made.

And I will close with the eloquent words of John Hanby:

“What often gets lost in consideration of an apologist’s ministry, when one looks at the amount of events, online views, book sales, testimonies, etc. is conversely the amount of people who are negatively impacted. There’s no easy way of measuring success versus failure. I’m reminded that the vast majority of online skeptics or critics of Christianity were former Christians, and a good number of those went to apologetics and were unsatisfied with the answers given. Maybe they were question begging, involved a non-sequitur, or didn’t truly address their underlying worry. I think of Drew from Genetically Modified Skeptic. Of course he’s not the most charitable person, nor does he give the impression of being unbiased, nor does he interact with the best defenders Christianity has to offer, nor does he fully grasp Theistic arguments. However, I imagine if when struggling with doubts in high school or college he had instead encountered Josh Rasmussen, his trajectory would likely be different. I’m reminded of that viral video where an Atheist scientist asks Ravi Zacharias about the Bible being debunked because of Evolution and there being no worldwide flood, and rather than doing the work of answering that involved question, he instead goes on a rant about materialism and quotes a David Berlinski zinger that is great for clips, prestige, and charisma [Christian OWNS Atheist with FACTS and LOGIC] yet leaves a curious skeptic unsatisfied and turned off from the project of Natural Theology.

**This is seriously harmful and not only deserves our attention, but indicates the need for improvement of large parts of popular apologetics. Full stop!**

I’m not saying that all apologists do a bad job. I think many popular apologists do a wonderful job. And criticizing pop-apologetics is not even most of what these “young apologists” do. I don’t even have one of these channels that nobody watches. David Pallmann has provided a systematic Wesleyan exegesis of various passages of the Bible, a ton of work on epistemology, the Synoptic problem, Gospel Reliability, and Intelligent Design. Christian Idealism has a bunch of content on Bayesian Epistemology, Philosophy of Science, Philosophy of Mind, Models of God, and with the help of Tim Howard and Josh Rasmussen developed an entire argument/explanatory framework for Theism on the basis of Unification. The scholarly discussions Than of Exploring Reality hosts on his channel, along with all the various objections to Christianity and Theism he engages speaks for itself. So this idea that Young Apologists have some unhealthy occupation with the apologetics they disagree with is false.”

Catholic Universalism: The Duality Model of Post-Mortem Salvation

By: Kyle Alander

Is Catholicism in principle incompatible with Universalism? Here I mean universalism in the strong sense, the view that we can expect or be highly confident in the truth of Universalism. The idea that if God exists then Universalism is most likely correct. My answer is that ‘yes’ it works, but only under a specific model of post-mortem salvation

This model attempts to present a vision of the afterlife that is both just and merciful.

Magisterial teachings

For eternal damnation its earliest champion is the Quicumque—or, if you prefer, the Athanasian Symbol—which ends:

And they that have done good shall go into life everlasting; and they that have done evil, into everlasting fire (ignem aeternum). This is the catholic faith; which except a man believe truly and firmly, he cannot be saved.

And then there’s Lateran IV (1215):

All of them will rise with their own bodies, which they now wear, so as to receive according to their deserts, whether these be good or bad; for the latter perpetual punishment (poenam perpetuam) with the devil, for the former eternal glory (gloriam sempiternam) with Christ.

And the First Council of Lyons (1245):

If anyone dies in mortal sin without repentance, beyond any doubt, he will be tortured forever (perpetuo cruciatur) by the flames of everlasting hell (aeternae gehennae).

With this we can see that the clear teaching is that hell is both eternal (unending) and those who enter it cannot get out (due to their unrepentant nature). Furthermore, The Council of Trent prohibits subjective certainty in regards to salvation

Trent’s decree on justification (1547):

No one, so long as he lives in this mortal condition, ought to be so presumptuous (praesumere debet) about the hidden mystery of divine predestination as to determine which certainty that he is definitely among the number of the predestined, as if it were true either that the one justified cannot sin anymore or that, if he sins, he should promise himself an assured repentance (certam resipiscentiam). For without special revelation (ex speciali revelatione) it is impossible to know whom God has chosen for himself.

Canon 15: If anyone says that a man who has been reborn and justified is bound by faith to believe that he is certainly among the number of the predestined (se certo esse in numero praedestinatorum), let him be anathema.

Canon 16: If anyone says that he has absolute and infallible certitude (certo habiturum absoluta et infallibili certitudine) that he will surely have the great gift of perseverance to the end (in finem), unless he has learned this by a special revelation (ex speciali revelatione), let him be anathema.

Understanding Sin and Salvation


At the heart of this duality model is the concept of sin as a privation of good (privatio boni). Sin is not an independent entity but a distortion or absence of the good. It’s like a parasite, existing solely by feeding on its host – the good within us. This creates a ‘false self,’ a shadowy existence shaped by sin, distinct from our true self or hypostasis. Imagining sin as a virus provides a vivid metaphor. Like a virus, sin embeds itself into our being, gradually shaping a ‘false self,’ a distorted identity that feeds off our true essence. In this way sin begins to incarnate into us as a disordered version of ourselves

The Duality Model

Zimmerman’s model, initially intended to demonstrate a materialistic model of bodily resurrection, introduces the notion of “fission” or “budding” in the context of an organism’s life. He proposes that an organism’s life is a special event that continues as long as the organism exists, despite material changes.

In Sijuwade’s adaptation, this concept of “fission” is employed. The idea is that upon a post-mortem individual’s acceptance of God’s grace, their body in Hell and a perfect duplicate in the next world are created, representing a dual reality.

The Dual Nature of the Afterlife


The Sin-Infected Self in Hell: The individual’s original body, which is eternally located in Hell, represents the false self, burdened with the virus of sin. This entity embodies the consequences of the individual’s choices and actions during life.

The Pure Duplicate in Paradise: Simultaneously, a perfect duplicate of the individual is created in the next world. This duplicate represents the true self, freed from the corrupting influence of sin. It’s in this state that the individual can enter an everlasting Agápēic relationship with God.

Fission and Continuation of Life: The fission process allows for the continuation of life in two separate realms. The post-mortem individual’s life continues with the body in the next world, which becomes the candidate for the continuation of the pre-fission life.

The concept of fission and its application to hell:

At the moment of death, particularly for an individual who dies in a state of mortal sin without repentance, a significant metaphysical event occurs. This event is the initiation point for a fission process that breaks apart a person into two separate entities.

Original Body and the Duplicate: The fission process results in the creation of two entities:

A. The original body, which carries the consequences of the individual’s sins, remains in Hell. This entity represents the persistence of the sinner’s identity as it was at the moment of death, eternally separated from God due to its state of sin.

B. Simultaneously, a perfect duplicate of the individual is created. This duplicate is free from the corrupting influence of sin and is capable of entering into a salvific relationship with God. This entity represents the individual’s potential for redemption and communion with God as they are no longer infected with the virus of sin

This process involves immanent causal connections that link the original body in Hell to the duplicate in the next world. Despite the physical separation, these connections ensure that both entities are, in some sense, continuations of the individual’s pre-death life.

God imparts a miraculous ability to the atoms comprising the individual’s body at the moment of death. This power enables the atoms to ‘bud’ or replicate, creating the duplicate in a different, heavenly realm. The original arrangement of atoms remains in Hell, sustaining the identity of the sin-infected self, while the replicated arrangement in Heaven constitutes the pure, redeemed self.

This fission results in the individual existing in two states simultaneously: as the sin-laden self in Hell and as the redeemed self in Paradise. The Life, or the animating principle, of the post-mortem individual follows the duplicate into Paradise, signifying that the true essence or potential of the individual is aligned with salvation and communion with God.

Theological Implications

  1. Radical Purification in Hell (Fission Model):
    • Dual Existence: Upon death, an individual facing damnation experiences a fission-like event. This event results in the creation of two entities: the original individual who continues to exist in a state of damnation, and a duplicate that embodies the potential for salvation.
    • Psychological and Physical Transformation: The original individual in hell undergoes a deep, possibly painful, transformative process. This transformation could involve a complete restructuring of their psyche and a fundamental change in their physical or spiritual form.
    • Total Replacement: The essence of this process is not merely the purification of existing traits but a total replacement or renewal of one’s nature. This could be viewed as a radical form of God’s grace, working to bring about a state of salvation even from the depths of damnation.
  2. Soft Purification in Purgatory:
    • Gradual Purification: Unlike the radical transformation in hell, purgatory involves a more gradual process. Here, souls undergo cleansing and preparation for heaven without the need for a complete overhaul of their identity.
    • Refinement of Existing Traits: The process in purgatory focuses on refining and purifying existing traits and dispositions, aligning them more closely with divine will and love.
  3. Theological Implications:
    • God’s Radical Grace: The fission model in hell can be seen as a manifestation of God’s radical grace and mercy, offering salvation even in the bleakest situations.
    • Diverse Paths to Salvation: This model suggests diverse paths to salvation – a radical transformation for some and a softer, refining process for others, depending on their spiritual state at the time of death.


The model also aligns with the Council of Trent’s prohibition of subjective certainty, as it emphasizes our limited understanding of which aspect of our identity will achieve salvation. This uncertainty stems from our incomplete self-knowledge; we cannot definitively know our true selves until we are revealed by the flames of hell. We can also get another aspect of this model

  1. Purgatory as Healing Through Purifying Fire:
  • Therapeutic Process: Purgatory is akin to a spiritual chemotherapy where the soul undergoes a healing process. This involves a profound self-examination and purification, much like how chemotherapy targets and eradicates disease cells.
  • Purification of the True Self: The focus in purgatory is on healing the wounded nature of one’s true self. It’s a process of purging impurities and aligning the soul more closely with divine goodness.
  • Eternal Effect: The effects of this purifying fire are eternal in the sense that the spiritual maladies it heals do not recur. The purification ensures a permanent alignment with divine will.

2. Hell as the Burning Away of the Corrupted Self:

  • Intense Purification: In hell, the purifying fire acts more intensely, targeting the deeply ingrained wounds, sins, and parasitic elements of the self. It’s a process of burning away the corrupted aspects of one’s identity.
  • Painful Letting Go: The attachment to the corrupted self makes this process painful, as it involves a conscious decision to let go of these deeply ingrained parts of oneself.
  • Christ’s Presence: The Incarnation plays a crucial role in this process. Christ’s descent into the very being of the soul ensures its survival through the flames. In a sense, Christ accompanies each soul, ensuring that no one undergoes this purification alone.

Thus, the purifying fire experienced after death is a transformative process aimed at healing the soul and aligning it with divine love. Whether experienced as purgatory or hell, it represents God’s unwavering commitment to the salvation of each soul, with Christ’s presence ensuring that no soul is left to face this journey alone.

Answering Objections:

Now some will object that we dont get this picture of a purifying hell from the scriptures. But they would be wrong. The passages that speak of “weeping and gnashing of teeth” or “torture” do not imply a non-purification process.

First the term “weeping and gnashing of teeth” does not imply physical torture

The phrase “weeping and gnashing of teeth,” commonly found in passages like Luke 13:28, does not necessarily imply perpetual physical suffering. A close examination of such references reveals that they do not explicitly state that this expression of distress continues indefinitely. For instance, Luke 13:28 focuses on the immediate response of the unsaved at the moment of judgment, as they witness the salvation of others and come to terms with their own exclusion. It does not, however, indicate that this state of weeping and gnashing of teeth is eternal.

Therefore, from a universalist perspective, these scriptural images are acknowledged as valid, yet they do not preclude the possibility of post-mortem repentance and redemption. The texts primarily convey the immediate emotional response to judgment without making definitive statements about the eternal state of the individuals involved. This understanding underscores a view of purgatory as a realm of spiritual purification and transformation, where the consciousness state of the false selves, shaped by sin and separation, undergoes a process of healing and realignment towards divine communion.

Now what if we ignored this and simply spoke about “torture”? Certainly, it’s reasonable to consider that the expressions of weeping and gnashing of teeth, indicative of emotions like sorrow and frustration, imply the existence of a living being capable of experiencing these emotions which can be torture? This notion raises an interesting point in the discussion about the nature of hell: for these expressions of emotion to occur, wouldn’t it necessitate that the individual is alive in some form in hell?

The issue is that even if we reduce “weeping and gnashing of teeth” to “torment” this still wouldn’t call into question the purification. In fact the world “torment” found in Revelation 14:10, is derived from the Greek word “basanizo,” which primarily conveys the concept of testing or proving, similar to how a touchstone is used to verify the purity of metals. This interpretation suggests that the lake of fire depicted in the passage might serve more as a means of “testing” rather than for inflicting torment or destruction. The imagery employed here draws a parallel to the process of assessing the genuineness and purity of metals using a touchstone. Viewing “basanizo” as a process of testing aligns with the idea of hell serving as a place where the soul’s true nature and attachments are revealed and refined. This is not merely punitive; instead, it’s a deeply transformative process, like purifying metal, where impurities are burned away, leaving behind what is true and valuable. In this framework, the soul’s journey through hell can be seen as a necessary passage through spiritual purification. The individual’s original self, which remains in hell, experiences this purification as a form of testing, burning away the dross of sin and spiritual corruption. So as the soul undergoes this testing, the process of “fission” or “budding” occurs and through this a perfect duplicate of the individual is created and placed in a state of salvation, unencumbered by the impurities being purged in hell. This duplicate represents the purified essence of the individual, now free to enter into a loving relationship with God. So while the original self remains in hell, undergoing continual testing and purification, the duplicate exists in a state of eternal communion with God.

This idea seems to fit with 1 Corinthians 3:13–15,

… each man’s work will become evident; for the day will show it because it is to be revealed with fire, and the fire itself will test the quality of each man’s work. If any man’s work which he has built on it remains, he will receive a reward. If any man’s work is burned up, he will suffer loss; but he himself will be saved, yet so as through fire.

The strong universalist stance is that at eventually, everyone will be healed (1 Corinthians 3:15 – If any man’s work burn, he shall suffer loss; but he himself shall be saved, yet so as by fire.) And the language of the NT in regards to what the torture of hell actually will be like supports this perspective. Furthermore given the unending nature of this radical purifying hell then the concept of eternal destruction of false selves actually plays a more significant role than merely contributing to beatitude; it is an essential element in its realization. The obliteration of these sin-constructed identities is fundamental to achieving true blessedness. In this context then Hell serves as a purifying force, ensuring the eternal well-being of the redeemed by permanently eradicating the damage caused by sin. This process guarantees that the sanctified, having been freed from their corrupted selves, will forever remain untouched by the destructive influence of sin forever

Someone may still object that the false selves experience endless suffering and so it is unjust. However, in the context of hell and the afterlife, the determination of the consciousness state of the false selves—whether they are non-conscious, subconscious, or at a diminished level of consciousness—is a subject ripe for further research and theological contemplation. The term “torture,” often associated with physical pain, is understood differently in this theological framework. It is interpreted more as a metaphorical or spiritual process, similar to the testing of metals with a touchstone, as suggested by the language of the New Testament. This interpretation aligns with a view of purgatory and hell as a place of purification rather than physical torment. Therefore, the Church’s teachings on these matters should be closely tied to the New Testament’s descriptions and implications.

What about evangelization?

A common critique against universalism is the concern that it might diminish the urgency and motivation for evangelism. However, this perspective overlooks a crucial aspect of the Christian mission. Consider the analogy of a grave illness: if we knew of a way to alleviate the suffering of someone afflicted with a severe disease, wouldn’t we be compelled to help make their healing process as smooth and painless as possible?

In the context of universalism, the concept of salvation is not confined to the afterlife; it begins here in our current existence. The role of sharing the Gospel, then, is akin to guiding others towards a path of lesser suffering and greater fulfillment in this life, in preparation for the hereafter. The world benefits immensely from having as many individuals as possible who embody the teachings and spirit of Christ, thereby nurturing the souls of many.

Therefore, the notion that universalism could dampen the zeal for missionary work is unfounded. If anything, understanding that everyone is ultimately destined for salvation can inspire a deeper commitment to spreading the Gospel. It emphasizes the importance of easing the spiritual journey for others, both in this life and beyond, and enriching their earthly experience with the love and grace that the message of Christ offers.

Conclusion

The Duality Model of Post-Mortem Salvation presents a unique synthesis of traditional Catholic doctrine and universalist theology. It offers a unique understanding of the afterlife, where the eternal consequences of sin and the possibility of salvation coexist in a metaphysical balance. This model upholds the teachings of eternal damnation while also embracing the universalist notion that all souls, ultimately, are destined for salvation.

By viewing sin as a distortion of the good and understanding salvation as a transformative process, this model aligns with both scriptural teachings and the enduring principles of the Church. It provides a framework for understanding the complex dynamics of sin, redemption, and the afterlife, offering hope and a deeper understanding of God’s grace and mercy.

In this view, the journey through hell and purgatory is not just a punitive measure, but a necessary path of purification and healing. It reaffirms the centrality of Christ’s redemptive work and the Church’s mission in guiding souls towards a lesser suffering and a more fulfilled existence, both in this life and the next. Universalism, in this context, becomes a testament to God’s unwavering commitment to the ultimate salvation of every soul, a beacon of hope in the face of eternal damnation, and a call to live out the Gospel with renewed fervor and compassion.

Footnotes

All council quotes are from Denzinger, Enchiridion

This model was originally proposed by Joshua Sijuwade, see: https://philarchive.org/archive/SIJATA#:~:text=Abstract%3A%20This%20article%20aims%20to,tionship%20of%20love%20with%20God.

See also this for a similar model: https://afkimel.wordpress.com/2019/09/22/may-catholics-endorse-universalism/

How Legal Positivism destroyed Roe

Note: This is an extended version of an essay I wrote for my philosophy of law course in college. I do not intend to defend or critique the morality of abortion but rather that from a legal philosophy perspective it is clear that the courts decision to overturn Roe V. Wade was based on the Legal Philosophy of H.L.A. Hart and by assuming his legal theory, Roe was doomed from the start

By: Kyle Alander

Doobs vs Jackson was a Supreme Court decision overturning Roe v. Wade and Casey v. Planned Parenthood. The decision of the Court was controversial and many wanted to blame the bias of the pro-life judges who dominated the court. However, I will argue that it was the philosophy of legal positivism developed by Hart that ultimately brought about the decision to declare abortion as not protected by the Constitution. Roe held that the abortion rights are part of a right to privacy that springs from the First, Fourth, Fifth, Ninth, and Fourteenth Amendments. The Casey Court then further made its declaration solely on the theory that the right to obtain an abortion is part of the “liberty” protected by the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause. Doobs v. Jackson did not find the arguments for this persuasive for a variety of reasons but I will focus on the underlying philosophy.


Before we get into why the court made the right decision assuming the truth of legal positivism I want to address a fundamental objection that people may bring up. Some may object to my analysis on the basis that I have not responded to the dissenting court’s arguments in this essay. However, arguments are dependent on theories in my view and when it comes to court cases, an argument only comes after one’s legal philosophy. So legal arguments only work in the context of the underlying logic of a specific legal theory. In this sense one has to assume a certain legal tradition prior to forming legal arguments. A legal argument cannot be divorced from a legal philosophy. With these considerations it is important that we examine the underlying legal philosophy and legal systems as a whole when investigating these sorts of disputes. For the purposes of this essay, I will be assuming Hart’s legal positivism as a given and apply it to this court case.

H.L.A. Hart’s legal positivism, fundamentally differentiates law from morality, arguing that a law’s validity stems from its adherence to established legal rules, not moral standards. Central to his theory is the ‘rule of recognition,’ a higher-order rule that helps identify valid laws within a legal system, thereby distinguishing legal directives from other social norms. Hart categorizes legal rules into ‘primary’ (directives of conduct for the populace) and ‘secondary’ (rules governing the creation and interpretation of primary rules). He also emphasizes the ‘internal point of view,’ where members of a society internalize and accept legal rules as legitimate standards. Although acknowledging judicial discretion in ‘hard cases,’ Hart insists this should align with the legal system’s principles. His philosophy underscores the autonomy of legal systems and clarifies the structured nature of judicial decision-making. With this theory in the background, let’s see how this shapes the abortion case.


First is that abortion is (i) not mentioned in constitutional law, (ii) was not passed federally in a legislative body at any point in the history of the legal system, and therefore has zero legal precedence within a positivist framework. To support (i) I claim that constitutional law requires a right to be either explicit or implicit. The Constitution does not clearly state an abortion is a right explicitly in the text. Thus any inference that the constitution lays out a right can only be implicit. However, even implicitly it is doubtful whether it states this. The First, Fourth, Fifth, Ninth, and Fourteenth Amendments are the only possible places it can be implicit. The First Amendment makes no implicit reference to anything to do with abortion, the Fourth Amendment only applies to unreasonable searches and seizures of property or identity and nothing to do with the reproductive system. The Fifth Amendment only applies to criminal procedures to individuals who were accused of a crime, the ninth amendment is used as a reference to the right of privacy and, finally, the fourteenth amendment is used as a reference to the due process clause.


For the right of privacy argument, there are two responses, first Roe’s privacy argument relied on equating the right to shield information from disclosure and the right to make a personal decision of abortion without governmental interference. The two are not the same and without further clarification by the law on what the right to privacy entails, it is doubtful that the privacy argument works. Second, it drew an arbitrary line in the viability of the fetus such that the “right of privacy” would be arbitrarily cut off at some time. The Roe court decision did not justify its trimester schema of when the right to privacy would be present and then disappear once the fetus had reached a certain development. We now turn our attention to the due process clause argument from Casey. Here my response is that due process only applies to criminal legal proceedings. The entire logic of Casey only works if the logic of Roe works and the Casey court did not add any new arguments for why abortion is constitutional independent of the privacy argument provided in Roe.


With this in mind in support of (ii) there is no point in history where abortion was passed as a legal right in any legislative bill and it does not fit the United States legal traditions. So Abortion was never essential to this Nation’s schema of liberty. Therefore since all arguments for legal precedence have been refuted there is no mention of abortion either explicitly or implicitly in the constitution and therefore the court went too far in declaring it a right without a legislative body.


Building up my case first, since abortion is not in the constitution then it should be contingent on the states until there is federal legislative support. This is important since a fundamental rule in legal positivism is the rule of recognition. Any federal laws on abortion must be recognized by a federal legislative body. But it has not been recognized as such and thus violates the rule of recognition. Hence the states should have the right to pass laws and enforce them since state rights and decisions on criminal matters clearly do have legal precedence in the legal system. Secondly, Roe and Casey extended the law beyond what the purpose of the law was. This is where pedigree is important to take into account. The pedigree of a legal rule is linked to its historical development, social acceptance, and recognition within the legal system. It is argued that Dobbs v. Jackson was based on pedigree since abortion is a penumbral case and this is where pedigree becomes important. The positivism of Hart takes the idea of pedigree as an application of family resemblances, here one must stay consistent with legal precedence and not invent new rules that are not valid by the rule of recognition. And in the case of abortion, there is zero legal precedence for it as it is not explicitly or implicity in the constitution and was not passed by legislation. Therefore given pedigree the Roe court went too far as it wasn’t something that passed the criteria of recognition.


Now one counter-argument to my entire case is that abortion is precisely a penumbral case, as the writers of the constitution didn’t have abortion in mind as a right and so morality should play a role in the legality of abortion. Hence the legal question is reduced to the moral question and since the court cannot make moral decisions assuming legal positivism then they should have kept Roe as valid until the moral question was answerable by the ethicist. Here I offer three lines of response.

The first is that the pro-life view of the morality of abortion could be correct and therefore we ought to have made abortion illegal if we are to use morality in such a penumbral case. We cannot just assume the pro-choice side is correct on the moral question. Second, while it is a penumbral case it still requires the rule of recognition to be a valid law which it clearly does not satisfy. There is no federal legal precedence for abortion access since state and federal law need to be separate under the United States legal system. Finally and perhaps the biggest issue at hand is that concepts like “liberty” do not have a well-defined robust recognition. Any and all rights and liberties not explicit in the Constitution serve as penumbral cases, should we then make morality be the deciding factor in all of them? In positivism, the moral implications are quite secondary. The new penumbral case must resemble older cases in order for morality to play any role. However, abortion is (i) morally controversial and so doesn’t deserve to be settled on purely moral grounds and (ii) doesn’t share any family resemblance to previous cases dealing with rights and liberties even if we take the case as not having any moral implications.


In Summary, there is no legal precedence for abortion in federal law or the Constitution. This implies that Roe v. Wade and Casey v. Planned Parenthood both violated the rule of recognition and therefore within a positivist legal framework the decision of Doobs vs Jackson to overturn these cases was correct. Attempts to argue that abortion is a penumbral case and therefore should be decided on moral grounds do not work given that abortion is (i) a controversial moral issue and so doesn’t deserve the same moral privilege as previous decisions made about liberties and rights and (ii) abortion does not share any family resemblances to previous cases involving the concept of “liberty” and so pedigree does not extend far enough to include abortion as a right to be had in the federal legal system.

A Short Abductive Argument for Theism

Note: This was the very first philosophy paper I wrote as a semester final in community college. It was in my introduction to philosophy course that I took back in 2021. So while I agree with what is said in this paper it is far far inferior to the methodology I now adopt, one can learn a lot in 2 years. Anyways even though I don’t fully endorse the methodology and arguments employed here I still want to share it. Enjoy! 

By: Kyle Alander

Theism vs Naturalism

I will propose a way to make progress on the question of God’s existence. I will begin by laying out limitations of traditional approaches in terms of giving deductive or inductive arguments for or against the existence of God. Then I will show the problems with framing theism as if it is adding into naturalistic commitments. Finally, I will seek to show that theism enjoys certain theoretical virtues that naturalist rivals lack. My purpose is not to decisively show that theism is true, but to illustrate a strategy for making progress on this big question about the ultimate nature of reality.

There are many different kinds of arguments that have been offered for and against the existence of God. Arguments for the existence of God come in the following classification; ontological arguments, cosmological arguments, teleological arguments, moral arguments and variations of other arguments. Arguments against the existence of God comes in the following classification: arguments from evil, arguments from divine hiddenness and variations of other arguments. While there are many arguments for and against the existence of God, they all have limitations. One popular argument for God is the Kalam cosmological argument. But this argument in all its versions all rely on causal finitism which is a metaphysical assumption about the impossibility of causal infinities (Malpass, Wes Moriston 2020) .

Furthermore, the Aristotelian proof or Aquinas’s five ways rely on many background assumptions related to the metaphysical systems they operate in. They would not work if something like existential inertia is true according to which concrete temporal objects tend to persist in existence without requiring an existential sustaining cause (Oppy 2019; Schmid 2020) . The arguments only work in the context of their metaphysics. One has to establish these metaphysical systems are correct before we can make a successful argument for God. The same is true for arguments against God. Arguments from evil operate on utilitarian and consequentialist assumptions (Reitan 2000). They cannot be divorced from a normative ethical theory of what God should do as it relates to evil. Arguments from evil would not work under an agent-based theory of normative ethics (Zagzebski 1996) . We need to establish a normative ethical theory in order to make a successful argument against God. 

With these considerations it is important that we examine the metaphysical and ethical systems as a whole when investigating these sorts of philosophical disputes. We should make a comparative assessment of our best theories using simplicity, fitness with data, explanatory scope, predictive power and so on (Oppy 2015). Theoretical virtues can be subsumed into two basic principles; Simplicity and Explanatory power. With Simplicity there is Syntactic Simplicity and Ontological Simplicity. 

The philosopher Graham Oppy presents a cumulative argument against God using Ontological Simplicity . He argues that theism includes all of the commitments of naturalism but adds additional supernatural commitments to it (Oppy 2014). By contrast, the philosopher Richard Swinburne uses more of Syntactical Simplicity to argue that Theism explains everything with one fundamental entity, whereas Naturalism has more complexity (Swinburne 2004) . We need to begin to compare the best version of Theism against the best competitive version of Naturalism.

To lay out a Theistic theory it’s important to start off with God’s ultimate nature so we can understand its implications. God’s ultimate nature would be ideal or absolute perfection. Ideal perfection would have the greatest concentration of purely positive qualities such as limitless value. From this we can deduce all of the particular perfections. One core simple property of absolute perfection can deduce the other perfections such as omnipotence, omniscience, omnibenevolence and so forth. God’s attributes are all derived from ideal perfection that is simple at its foundational core. 

On the other side we have Naturalism. On naturalism all that exists is natural causal entities and powers. A Naturalism that precludes Theism would claim that reality is made of fundamental mindless matter and we are just arrangements of such matter. Consciousness would be produced by the brain and moral facts may or may not be objective. If there are objective moral facts or duties we may say that they are necessary truths. Which means they cannot be false in any possible world. While not all versions of Naturalism preclude Theism the ones that do are what we should compare to Theism. The main difference between Theism and Naturalism, then, is that Theism has ideal perfection as the foundation to reality whereas Naturalism has imperfection as the foundation. 

To begin our comparison I first dispute that theism is adding to naturalistic commitments. Consider that naturalism posits fundamental imperfection (or an infinite chain of dependent things). This posit adds complexity and bruteness to naturalism (Leftow 2017). If fundamental reality is whatever physics says (whether particles, fields or some initial state), then even if there is an infinite chain of these things it is a brute fact that such things exist. 

To reply, a naturalist might appeal to necessity. Perhaps instead of supposing that some imperfection is brute, we could explain the fundamental imperfection in terms of its necessary existence. However, I don’t think this reply works because it only pushes the bruteness back a step: we can now ask why do such things exist necessarily?

Theism, by contrast, provides a way to eliminate brute necessities. For ideal perfection would entail necessary existence, since necessary existence is a particular perfection. In this way, ideal perfection has an internal nature that can explain its own necessity given its ideal perfection. By contrast there’s nothing about the internal nature of some imperfect foundation that would explain its own necessary existence (Byerly 2019) . On naturalism, it is simply a brute fact that things exist, or naturalism is left with unexplained necessities. Theism has a foundational explanation and so it gets rid of fundamental bruteness and provides more explanatory depth

Second, consider that Naturalism posits natural objects. However, the naturalist has to specify that these objects are mind-independent and beyond our immediate experience. We have direct awareness of experience, but not a world beyond experience (Kastrup 2018). The Theist can shave these off by holding to an idealistic ontology of mental monism where only experience exists. A world of just experience is compatible with an external world as long as the things you experience only exist in someone’s experience which can be personal experience or trans-personal experience (Kastrup 2017). Instead of posting some brute world beyond and independent from experience or posting fundamental unexplained necessities we can explain necessities and shave off all mind-independent objects to stick with an experiential ontology on theism. 

These considerations help to turn the tables in the comparison of naturalism vs theism. Instead of adding God to the physical universe we are instead simplifying the foundations of reality by getting rid of brute facts to provide explanatory depth and shaving off the mindless matter of a world beyond experience. It seems that theism and naturalism have totally different conceptions of the universe but in final count theism has the simpler conception when we only have an experiential ontology to the universe. 

Finally, consider that we want a hypothesis that explains the most with the least. On naturalism you can have the explanatory scope needed to account for facts of the world without God. These facts include logic, mathematics, consciousness, fine tuning, morality, religious experience and awareness expanding adventures. However if they do so with a naturalism that precludes theism then they will add fundamental complexity to the theory. They may posit an abundance of different necessities or separated explanations to explain things like logic, morality and fine tuning. 

Theism on the other hand can explain all of these by one fundamentally perfect necessity. Ideal perfection entails perfect goodness which serves as the moral foundation of all moral principles. Ideal perfection entails perfect knowledge which serves as the foundation of all principles of reason and mathematics. Ideal perfection entails perfect power which serves as the resources to create a world suitable for other minds which can have their own personal experiences to build identities. Ideal perfection successfully explains everything relevant to its own ontology since it internally has the resources to explain its own necessary existence as well as logical, mathematical and moral truths. Theism has the simple unification needed to explain the most with the least and does not require separated explanations since all aspects of reality converge into a single perfect source 

In summary, all arguments for and against God rely on prior metaphysical theories and so we should employ theoretical virtues and compare such metaphysical theories. My conclusion is that Theism as a metaphysical theory beats Naturalism on at least these grounds: (i) eliminates all brute facts and thus has more explanatory depth, (ii) provides the simplest conception of the universe, and (iii) provides a more unified account of all necessary truths. This of course does not settle the debate on God’s existence but my goal is to have pointed out the theoretical virtues that favor theism against naturalism. 

Works cited

Byerly, T Ryan. “From a Necessary Being to a Perfect Being.” Analysis, vol. 79, no. 1, 2018, pp. 10–17., doi:10.1093/analys/any009. 

 Kastrup, Bernardo. “An Ontological Solution to the Mind-Body Problem.” Philosophies, vol. 2, no. 4, 2017, p. 10., doi:10.3390/philosophies2020010.

Kastrup, Bernardo. “Conflating Abstraction with Empirical Observation: The False Mind-Matter Dichotomy.” Academia.edu, 2018, http://www.academia.edu/37049147/Conflating_Abstraction_with_Empirical_Observation_The_False_Mind_Matter_Dichotomy.

LEFTOW, BRIAN. “A Naturalist Cosmological Argument.” Religious Studies, vol. 53, no. 3, 2017, pp. 321–338., doi:10.1017/s0034412517000257.

Malpass, Alex, and Wes Morriston. “Endless and Infinite.” The Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 70, no. 281, 2020, pp. 830–849., doi:10.1093/pq/pqaa005.

Oppy, G. Best Argument against God. Palgrave Pivot, 2014.

OPPY, GRAHAM. “On Stage One of Feser’s ‘Aristotelian Proof.’” Religious Studies, 2019, pp. 1–12., doi:10.1017/s0034412519000568. 

OPPY, GRAHAM. “What Derivations Cannot Do.” Religious Studies, vol. 51, no. 3, 2015, pp. 323–333., doi:10.1017/s0034412515000256.

Reitan, Eric. “Does the Argument from Evil Assume a Consequentialist Morality? – Volume 17, Issue 3, July 2000.” Faith and Philosophy, 16 Apr. 2021, http://www.pdcnet.org/faithphil/content/faithphil_2000_0017_0003_0306_0319.

Schmid, Joseph C. “Existential Inertia and the Aristotelian Proof.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 2020, doi:10.1007/s11153-020-09773-9. 

Swinburne, Richard. The Existence of God. Clarendon Press, 2004. 

Zagzebski, Linda. “An Agent-Based Approach to the Problem of Evil.” International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, vol. 39, no. 3, 1996, pp. 127–139., doi:10.1007/bf00136244. 

Stage 2 contingency arguments and Oppys objections to fine tuning

Note: This article was originally posted in the worldview design training center back in January of 2021, so it does not fully represent my current thoughts on the subject of fine tuning and how theism explains it (I think better objections to fine tuning exist in the literature and there are better ways to cash out how fine tuning favors theism). But I think it still provides a reasonable response to Oppys specific objection 

By: Kyle Alander

One of the things I have been thinking deeply on is Graham Oppy’s objections to the fine tuning argument. Probably the most powerful one from him is an objection he presents in his book “The best argument against God” he presents a dilemma in this way

If we are comparing (i) a view that says that it is a brute fact that parameters take a value from a given range with (ii) a view that says that parameters were chosen to take a value from the same range, but it is simply a brute fact that this particular choice was made-It is very hard to see why we should think that one view affords a more satisfactory explanation than the other. Could God have chosen to make a universe that lasts for less than a second? Could God have chosen to make a universe that blows apart so rapidly that it is mostly empty space?. If we suppose that the answer to either these questions as affirmative, then we cannot also say that God must have all things considered reason to prefer a life permitting universe to one of these non-life permanent alternatives. But if God needed had all things considered reason to refer a life permitting universe to one of these non-life permitting alternatives, then, on the assumption that God’s choosing is a brute fact It surely does turn out that theist has no better explanation than naturalist of why it is that relevant cosmic parameters take the parameters that they do (The best argument against God, 29-30)

Basically Oppys objection is that any reason God has for creating a life permitting universe is a brute fact. And so that is no better than a naturalist positing that cosmic fine tuning are brute facts. Thus fine tuning gives us no reason to prefer Theism over Naturalism. From what I can see this objection works only if we ignore an important distinction of brute facts. I think Theism has an advantage in fine tuning due to it being brutiness reducing. I discovered this when reading Brian Leftows work . Here is what Brian Leftow says in response to Graham Oppy on Swinburne’s inductive arguments 

For every brute fact about the natural world, on theism there is an equally brute divine intention that it be so. One might therefore claim that theism “doubles” the brute facts there are on naturalism. I reply that it does not. On theism, these facts about the natural are not brute. The corresponding divine intentions causally explain them. If the intentions are brute, they do not add to reality’s overall bruteness. They merely relocate it. I think that some of God’s particular intentions are indeed brute. I think that ultimately, God “just picks” some features of the universe, without a full sufficient reason for His pick- e.g. making n stars rather than n+1. Even so, His beliefs and desires may make these less brute than the corresponding natural facts would be on naturalism. Suppose that I’m eating a peanut-butter and jelly sandwich. You ask why. I say “I was hungry.” That doesn’t tell you why I intended to eat a PB&J rather than something else, but it does tell you why I intended to eat. My intending to eat that particular sandwich is now less mysterious than it was; one aspect of that is fully explained, namely that I intended to eat. God intended a universe with features 1, 2… which are hospitable to our sort of life. Why 1, 2 etc.? Suppose I say that He wanted to cause our sort of life and so made the universe hospitable to it. That doesn’t fully answer the question, but it answers an aspect of it. It explains God’s having some intention to create some hospitable features, though not the intention to create 1, 2, etc. in particular rather than other hospitable features. That seems a genuine bruteness-reducer. I don’t see that naturalism can do the same with initial cosmic conditions, just because they are initial. So even if there are as many brute particular divine intentions as there would be brute particular natural facts on naturalism, theism can make some of them less brute. When we fill the views out, less is brute about God on perfect being theism than about the fundamental natural on naturalism. Having less brute at the fundamental level is a theoretical virtue. (It may even be one reason we think parsimony important.) Here theism is ahead. So far, then, it seems that perfect being theism can explain more of the natural than naturalism can, with equal explanatory power (as Oppy concedes), and leave less brute at the fundamental level in doing so. Theism’s extra ontology buys a lot. Explaining what puzzles us and reducing fundamental brutality may more than offset its cost. I know no algorithm for weighing these things, but to me, at least, it seems so far that overall, theism gets no worse than a tie. I now argue that on two of Oppy’s “shapes,” it is ahead. If this is so, then on balance, across all branches, theism is ahead” (Brian Leftow, a naturalist cosmological argument, 8-9) 

I believe that Dr. Brian Leftow makes a good point here. So I’ve come up with this distinction. We have full brute facts and partial brute facts. Full brute facts are those like what Oppy proposes is the fine tuning. It’s just a brute fact that the cosmic parameters are the way they are. On theism however we only have partial brute facts because God’s reasons would flow from his nature. So Theism would have less brutiness at the foundation for reality than Naturalism would. For any explanation the Naturalist gives for any facts like fine tuning, consciousness, morality etc. They need to posit more brutiness in their metaphysics than the Theist does.

I think this brings us to a new thought I’ve been having which I call “brutiness reducing principles” these are more like tools to help us cross stage 2 contingency arguments. Stage 1 was crossed with the PSR (principle of sufficient reason). Now I think stage 2 can be crossed with brutiness-reducing principles. Here are a few proposals 

Occam’s Laser: Do not multiply fundamental entities without necessity

Occam’s Laser is an improvement on Occam’s razor and philosopher Jonathan Schaffer argues for this principle in his paper that discusses the simplicity of theories and he answers objections to the idea. This would have implications if combined with the next principle

Principle of Simple Unification (PSU): For any set of facts whether contingent and/or necessary that exist, there is a simple unifying root that unifies the contingent and/or necessary facts 

Now the PSU was an idea I came up with to help highlight the need for unification of theories. Currently there are not any papers written on it but I did a video that goes over how it has implications for naturalism. What I argue in basic terms is that when we talk about the facts of the world like consciousness, fine tuning, morality, religious experience etc.. The naturalist posits brute facts to explain it or at least they have to posit fundamental brutiness and separated explanation’s for things. Since the principle is new I’m going to go a little more in detail about it here to get people to understand the basic concepts. If we say that naturalism implies an imperfect foundation as Josh Rasmussen would argue there are some issues

An imperfect foundation requires multiple sources to ground different things. An imperfect foundation has to have a different sources to ground matter, mind, morals, reason and value. In fact one could say that an imperfect foundation may be only able to account for one of these things. So it may be able to explain the existence of matter but not able to explain the existence of morals, value or reason and so it has to have different sources for those things

A perfect foundation by contrast grounds all these things with only one source which is perfection. So a perfect foundation is simpler and can explain everything while an imperfect foundation would need to be more complex by having different sources for these different things. So then a perfect foundation explains all the complexities of the world by a simple root while an imperfect foundation does not. More features of reality are explained by a perfect simple root while imperfection lacks this explanatory power at its own simple root. 

Perfection is the root by which all things are explained. Imperfection doesn’t have the same root to explain mind, matter, morals, reason and value. In order for an imperfect foundation to be the explanation of reality one would have to say that there are many unexplained necessary truths. So then the reason that the universe is fine-tuned is because the universe is necessary or the foundational laws have to be a certain way. Or the reason that objective morality exists is because it is necessarily a part of our reasoning and the reason that mathematics is applicable to our universe is simply because it is necessary. However all of these things are unexplained necessary truths. They are all truths about the world that are just there without a simple foundational root. However a perfect foundation provides the root necessary to ground all necessary truths. And so since a perfect foundation has the least amount of unexplained necessary truths then it is a simpler hypothesis. On the perfect foundation, more of the necessary truths can be explained by the simple root . This speaks to explanatory power. Thus the simpler theory which has the fewest unexplained necessary truths will also be the one with the most explanatory power. 

When we combine the PSU with Occam’s Laser then theism would have the least amount of fundamental entities and it would be able to derive all the facts about the world rather than positing brute entities. Since fundamental perfection is the fundamental entity that can explain all of reality then there is no need to posit fundamental imperfection at the ground for reality and hence Theism is simpler and more unified than Naturalism

Finally a last one that I think could work is the principle of no arbitrary limits as argued by Josh Rasmussen

Principle of no fundamental arbitrary limits: Do not multiply fundamental unexplained/arbitrary limits at the foundation

I added the idea of “fundamental” limits because of an objection regarding the trinity. The trinity in God is a limit but its not a fundamental limit. So something with no fundamental limits would be able to have unlimited power. This includes the power to know things and the power of reason. Furthermore add in value and it cant have any fundamental limits in regards to its total value. Something with no limits to value can only be perfect and hence one is able to derive the traditional attributes of God from this limitless value. 

In conclusion, I think all of these principles can help to answer the objections that Graham Oppy has put forth as well as help us cross stage 2 of contingency argument’s. Stage 1 was crossed with the PSR (principle of sufficient reason). Now I think stage 2 can be crossed with these type of brutiness-reducing principles (only if one grants them of course). 

Citations (for those interested in the source material):

https://www.jstor.org/stable/pdf/26847912.pdf

https://philpapers.org/rec/OPPTBA

A response to Alex O Connors argument against Free Will

By: Kyle Alander

I recently listened to a discussion between Ben Shapiro and Alex O Connor on whether religion is good for society. I thought the discussion was overall balanced and helpful. I will write a later post about my full thoughts on the issue. However, at the beginning of the discussion, Alex decided to discuss free will with Ben and he brought forward an interesting objection that I wish to answer here. While I have defended free will elsewhere this argument from Alex is not part of my defense. Hence I will treat this argument as new and so worthy of response.

Alex O’Connor’s argument against free will can be formulated as a logical dilemma, focusing on the nature of the self and its decisions. Hence it does not rely on any view about the nature of the mind and the brain (something that I found helpful)

Here’s a structured formulation:

1. Alex’s Question: Is the self determined or undetermined?

2. Case 1 – Undetermined Self:
– Assertion: If the self is undetermined, then its actions and decisions are random.
– Conclusion: If actions are random, the individual cannot be in control of them.

3. Case 2 – Determined Self:
– Sub-Question: If the self is determined, is it determined by internal or external factors?
– Case 2A – External Determination:
– Assertion: If determined by external factors, the individual is not in control of those factors.
– Conclusion: Therefore, the individual is not in control of the self.
– Case 2B – Internal Determination:
– Assertion: If determined by internal factors, we must inquire what determines these internal factors.
– Recursive Question: Is the determinant of the internal factors itself determined or undetermined?
– Conclusion: This leads back to the original dilemma (step 1), creating an infinite regress.

4. Overall Conclusion: In either case (undetermined or determined), the individual lacks control over the self, challenging the concept of free will.

This formulation demonstrates a logical progression, examining each possibility (undetermined or determined) and its implications, ultimately leading to the conclusion that free will is problematic under either scenario. Based on the questions that Alex asked Ben this I believe is the best formulization of his argument.

———————————————————————–

Response:

Drawing from Peter Tse’s concept of second-order free will or metafree will one can offer a nuanced critique of Alex O’Connor’s argument against free will. Here’s how it specifically addresses and potentially dismantles parts of O’Connor’s argument:

Peter Tse describes another kind of free will which he calls second order free will or meta-free will

“Finally, it is not enough to simply have the ‘first-order free will’ afforded by the above kind of nervous system that can choose actions freely. Only if present choices can ultimately lead to a chooser becoming a new kind of chooser — that is, only if there is second-order free will or metafree will — do brains have the capacity to both have chosen otherwise, and to have meta-chosen otherwise. Only such a metafree will allows a brain to not only choose among options available now, but to cultivate and create new types of options for itself in the future that are not presently open to it . Only then can there be responsibility for having chosen to become a certain kind of person who chooses from among actions consistent with being that kind of person.” Dr. Peter Tse

Given this view this challenges Alex’s argument on several fronts:


1. Beyond the Binary of Determined/Undetermined:
– O’Connor’s argument hinges on a binary framework: the self is either determined or undetermined. Tse’s concept challenges this by introducing a more complex model where decision-making is not strictly binary but involves a dynamic interplay of factors.
– The idea of cultivating criteria and developing metafree will suggests that the self can evolve and shape its own decision-making criteria over time, which goes beyond the simple dichotomy of determined or undetermined.

2. Internal Determinism Revisited:
– O’Connor argues that if the self is determined by internal factors, it leads to an infinite regress. However, Tse’s model suggests that this internal determination is not a simple linear process but involves an active, conscious shaping of one’s future decision-making framework.
– This approach counters the idea of an infinite regress by suggesting that the brain’s capacity to evolve and create new decision-making criteria is a form of self-determination, not merely a reaction to pre-existing conditions.

3. Introduction of Dependent Determinism:
– O’Connor’s framework doesn’t seem to consider dependent determinism, where decisions are influenced by criteria that the individual actively cultivates. This type of determinism implies a form of agency that is missing from O’Connor’s dichotomy.
– In this model, the self is neither entirely controlled by external factors nor trapped in an infinite regress of internal factors. Instead, it actively engages in shaping its decision-making environment.

4. Addressing the Control Issue:
– O’Connor contends that if actions are random or determined by external factors, the individual lacks control. The concept of metafree will suggests a form of control that emerges from the individual’s capacity to shape future decision-making criteria and paths.
– This kind of control is neither purely random nor entirely pre-determined; it’s a product of the individual’s ongoing engagement with their own cognitive processes and their environment.

Here’s a deeper look into Peter Tses ideas:

1. Second-Order Free Will or Metafree Will:
– Tse argues that the brain’s ability to choose is not limited to immediate options; it extends to shaping future choices and creating new possibilities.
– This “second-order” free will means the brain can change the kind of chooser it is, thus expanding or altering the range of choices available in the future.
– It’s about the brain’s capacity not only to make choices based on current circumstances but also to influence and change its own decision-making framework over time.

2. Neural Basis of Free Will:
– Tse’s approach is grounded in neuroscience. He suggests that the neural mechanisms in the brain are not strictly deterministic in a classical sense. Instead, they allow for the emergence of new patterns and connections, which in turn lead to new types of choices and behaviors.
– He emphasizes the importance of neural plasticity – the brain’s ability to change and adapt – in facilitating this kind of free will.

3. Cultivating Criteria:
– In Tse’s view, every decision and action influences the brain’s future decision-making processes. By choosing certain paths, the brain effectively ‘cultivates’ certain criteria or values, which then inform future choices.
– This cultivation of criteria is a dynamic process, wherein the individual is not just a passive recipient of external influences but actively shapes their own cognitive and decision-making landscape.

4. Agency and Responsibility:
– Tse’s model implies a heightened sense of agency and responsibility. Since individuals have the capacity to shape their future selves through their choices, they bear responsibility for the kind of person they become.
– This view counters arguments that free will is an illusion due to deterministic or random processes, suggesting instead that individuals play a crucial role in their own self-development.

5. Critique of Traditional Determinism:
– Traditional determinism posits that all events are the result of preceding causes. Tse challenges this by proposing that the brain can function in a way that is not entirely predetermined by past states.
– His concept of free will suggests a more complex interplay between determinism, randomness, and conscious choice, where the brain’s capacity for self-modification plays a central role.

6. Implications for Consciousness and Selfhood:
– Tse’s theory also has significant implications for our understanding of consciousness and the self. It suggests that selfhood is a dynamic, ever-evolving process, shaped by our continuous engagement with our choices and their consequences.

In essence, Peter Tse’s view of free will is a unique model of free will that is more complex and interactive than traditional deterministic or indeterministic models, emphasizing the brain’s unique capacity for self-modification and the cultivation of decision-making criteria.

In summary, the response based on Peter Tse’s concept challenges the foundational assumptions of O’Connor’s argument by introducing a more complex understanding of free will. It suggests that free will can exist as a sophisticated interplay of evolving criteria, conscious decision-making, and the capacity to shape one’s future self, which goes beyond the simplistic binary of determined versus undetermined. This I believe puts to rest Alex’s argument

For more on Peter Tse, see: “Two types of libertarian free will are realized in the human ….” https://www.dartmouth.edu/~peter/pdf/C12.pdf.

A novel perspective on the evolution controversy

Note: This post is taken originally from something I wrote as part of the worldview design training center. I have decided to take what I have written their and put it in this blog. Enjoy! 

By: Kyle Alander

One of the most heated debates among Christians is how we are too see evolution. Some deny evolution and hold to a young universe (young earth creationist) . Some deny evolution and hold to an old universe (old earth creationism). 

There are those who lean towards a traditional understanding of evolutionary history but think that God must have supernaturally intervened in much of the events in that history. This can either be those that hold to intelligent design theory or those that hold to some variation of evolutionary creationism that requires divine intervention within certain events. So while one can hold a traditional view of the evolutionary history there are many events in that history that require supernatural intervention. 

Then there is what I will term *deistic evolution* where God just sets up the initial conditions and lets everything play out on its own. So God is sustaining the universe but is not responsible for much other things. The entire evolutionary history on this account is a totally natural process and nature is mindless and follows strict physical laws. 

Here I want to step back and look at the underlying assumptions being made in these views. While I do lean more towards theistic evolution (since I deny intelligent design theory and I accept the traditional evolutionary story of life on Earth) I have a new option that is consistent with a Christian understanding of nature rather than deism:

If Christians are too hold a view that rejects intelligent design theory and hold that evolution doesn’t require constant divine intervention and NOT commit themselves to deistic evolution I think Christians will need to change their views not on evolution but on their philosophy of nature

(1) Philosophy of Nature

Philosophy of nature asks about what is nature fundamentally? Here are two options: 

1. Nature is a blind and mindless machine that strictly obeys physical laws 

2. Nature is a cognitive and mental process that has intelligence built into it

Most scientists including Christians who hold to intelligent design or hold to a divine interventionist view of evolutionary creationism, and the neo-darwinist and the deistic evolutionist assume the first option. The idea of a mental aspect to nature is something that most scientists (of every persuasion) don’t generally consider. Nature is thought to obey rules (physical laws) mindlessly and strictly. And this assumption is held by people of all sides of the evolutionary controversy.

Those who hold to intelligent design or some variation of evolutionary creationism that requires divine intervention will assume without justification that nature is inherently mindless and non-intelligent and so assume that we need an external intelligent designer in order to account for the intelligence found in biological systems. 

(2) The novel approach to evolution

My view is to take the second option: Nature is a cognitive and mental process that has intelligence built into it

Taking this approach on the philosophy of nature bypasses a lot of issues. The Christian can say that God sustains a universe that has cognition already built into it (not human cognition but the type similar to plants). Taking this approach would bypass the intelligent design objections against evolution because they presuppose that nature doesn’t inherently have intelligence built into it. However if nature does have intelligence built into it then one does not require an intelligent design theory to account for this. If God created a universe that already has cognition built into it then one can be consistent with the idea that evolution was the total byproduct of nothing but natural processes and that natural processes themselves are cognitive and intelligent. As soon as we deny that nature is fundamentally mindless then that opens the door for an intelligent creation that can produce things on God’s behalf without God needing to do constant divine interventions. 

While intelligent design theorists are correct in that you cannot get intelligence from non-intelligence (or cognition from non-cognition). The intelligent design theorist are forgetting that if one’s philosophy of nature includes the fact that nature is itself intelligent and cognitive then that will explain the data that intelligent designers appeal to when trying to support their theory.

And so it is my view that God creating a universe that has cognition built into it and therefore can evolve intelligently on its own is more likely than God creating a mindless universe that requires constant divine intervention. It really comes down to one’s philosophy of nature. 

Conclusion

If nature is fundamentally mindless then it is expected that one will not be able to explain consciousness nor will they be able to explain the intelligence within biological systems. However if nature is fundamentally mental and cognitive then one will be able to explain the data of consciousness and intelligent biological systems within a theistic evolutionary framework. 

Response to Eclectic Media (Dhorpatan) on property dualism

Response to this video: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=pkE9A7-SOxQ
So he’s back! After a few years of being absent from creating youtube videos Eclectic media (I will be referring to as EM for the remainder of this post) has decided to do a video that refutes my blog post I made a few years back 1. Of course I don’t think he actually addresses the core point I want to tell my readers that I have learned a lot from when I last made that post a few years back. I have read a lot on the literature in philosophy of mind and have read both of David Chalmers books on consciousness 2,3. Likewise I have modified some of my own views on the subject and continue to learn as much as I can. I will admit when I’m wrong and will modify my view according to deal with the new information and it’s my goal in this response to clarify my own views and how a few of EM criticisms are partially valid. However as a final note I do not plan to do responses back and forth infinitely I will only do a response to a response to my original blog since I don’t plan to give EM or anyone else unlimited attention. I understand that people think that whoever gets the last word wins but I’m not going to respond to their response to my response to their response to my original blog (because I have a life) I simply do not have the patience or time. So if EM wants to respond again to this post that’s his freedom to do that but I won’t do anymore blog post directed at him and if the dispute continues then he can have a real debate with me on the topic but it won’t include blogs or videos. So now that i’ve gotten that out of the way let’s see what EM has to say.
He first responds to my first objection.
To start of at 0:40-1:00
“This is question begging because Alander has done nothing as far as I know to refute the position of direct realism of perception and as long as that is a logically coherent position a dualist can rationally say he does see material objects themselves”
He is right that I did not provide a refutation of direct realism so I will provide two main reasons why that view is wrong here. First there is an a priori reason why its wrong and it’s because we already know a place where direct realism is obviously false and that place is in the dreams we have.
The dream argument against direct realism
P1) If direct realism is true then our perceptions only display objects that actually exist
P2) objects in dreams aren’t real they are a mental construct
P3) dream worlds are indistinguishable from the real world unless you wake up
P4) our perceptions cause us to perceive unreal objects (2,3)
C) direct realism is false
Now this argument is only a priori it does not disprove direct realism in our world only direct realism in a dream world however this will lead me to the next main problem with direct realism and its that it has been directly falsified by quantum mechanics. First it should be noted that naive realism and direct realism are seen as the same thing4. And the view of naive realism was directly falsified

“No naive realistic picture is compatible with our results because whether a quantum could be seen as showing particle- or wave-like behavior would depend on a causally disconnected choice. It is therefore suggestive to abandon such pictures altogether.”5
So this falsifies direct realism scientifically. However even without these problems direct realism itself is just a big question begging assertion. It simply overlooks the epistemic problems of us living in the matrix or in other words it only assumes our perceptions are direct to a material world and thinks qualia is meaningless. Qualia is properly basic since even if the world was an illusion our perceptions would still appear to us as if they are real things. Direct realism is not properly basic while qualia is properly basic given that we can have doubts about the outside world but cannot doubt the appearances of the outside world. This gives us good reason to think qualia is a real thing and not just a linguistic confusion of the language we use to describe the world and that qualia is far more parsimonious and simple than direct realism given its a priori justification while the material ontology that property dualism requires is nothing more than a bare assertion. So either way my original point stands. We do not have contact with material objects only the appearance and qualia of them however these properly basic things themselves are mental in nature. You can describe the world we experience in terms of mental objects but it is much harder to describe our experiences as reducing to an ontology that is not itself mental.
Next he responds to objection 2 and I will clarify my position.
Continuing at 1:22-2:05
“First off this begs the question as alander does not explain why there is necessarily an epistemic gap and why there cannot in principle be an epistemic link. Second alander does not explain what he means by the subjective/objective gap and third even if we accept his critique of his epistemic gap that would not disprove property dualism since that is only epistemic and not ontological in other words there wouldn’t be an ontological problem but only an epistemic and informational problem”
I think this criticism is fair enough for the most part however I should mention a few things. First in my original objection I should have referenced the explanatory gap as that is the problem for how consciousness can be explained in pure physical terms and I should have mentioned that the epistemic gap is between mental and physical properties so his first two points are answered however when it comes to his third point he is correct but it was not my intention to disprove property dualism simply on the epistemic gap alone only that there is clearly an epistemic one. This goes back to my first objection that concerning “true scientific knowledge” that even if science is impossible under property dualism that itself is only epistemic as science is the epistemic tool of studying the outside world. So yes there is no true ontological problem with property dualism but there clearly is an epistemic problem with it and it is what I mentioned above. So in summary the first two objections in my original blog should be looked as the same problem rather than separate and I think EM criticism has shown me that this is in fact the case thus my response to him here will be the same arguments I gave above concerning direct realism and qualia.
Next he responds to my syllogism argument and I will lay out my original argument here and deal with is objections to it.
Original argument

P1) If solipsism is conceivable, then the universe could exist such that only mind exist in a possible world

P2) Solipsism is conceivable

C1) Thus the universe could exist with only the mind in it

P3) Universes can not only consist of properties or processes, but must also include entities and things for the properties to glue themselves onto

P4) There is no difference between a solipsistic mind and a mind in the actual world

C2) Thus the mind cannot be a property or a process but rather must be an entity
He first states that he does not think solipsism is logically possible and plans to do a future video on why that’s the case so I will not deal with that here however he does mention other objections to my argument which I will proceed to respond too.
2:20-4:10
EM: “Conceivability is not possibility but the problem is that this syllogism argument does not get kyle alander what he needs…he needs an argument to show that property dualism is logically impossible and that every possible world including the actual world consist of a solipsistic paradigm that has the mind as an entity rather than just a property or process but the syllogism does not give you a transworld exhibition…all it gives you is that if you accept the premises there is only one possible world where solipsism is true and in that possible world mind is an entity…but this does not force us to accept that this has to be true of all possible worlds…P4 is ridiculous there is clearly a difference between a solipsistic mind and a mind of the actual world. A solipsistic mind would be in which only the self exist while the mind in the actual world could be a mind where there is an external world outside the self”
I will divide this into different parts to respond to each claim accordingly.

1. EM: Conceivability is not possibility
Response: This is true however the claim was if solipsism is possible and I believe it is. First the mind and self is a priori while other thing are not. This of course doesn’t necessitate ontological solipsism but it does necessitate epistemic solipsism. Where we can only know about the contents of our minds but we cannot know anything beyond our minds. This is due to the fact that all our knowledge is grounded in our minds and that our minds are what justify our other beliefs about the world and also how we contain knowledge in the first place. Now because of this it is logically possible for solipsism to be true in a possible world since its the case a priori that all knowledge does reside only in our minds. In the matter of explanations and knowledge it is clear that conceivability is central. If it’s the case that all our knowledge is only in our minds then its also at least logically possible that there only exist one mind and that would infer ontological solipsism. The question of other minds will always arise and likewise something a priori such as the mind’s ability to recognise that it may possibility be the only thing that exist without the need for a separate material substance closes the gap between conceivability and possibility at least in the case of ontological solipsism.

2. EM: He needs to show that property dualism is logically impossible
Response: My argument does not attempt to show that property dualism is logically impossible only that it is not true in the actual world. And in my argument I do this by assuming solipsism is at least logically possible then making the point that universes cannot only exist with properties or processes but must have some type of substance or fundamental ontology (ontology being the nature of what things are) then finally showing that we cannot truly distinguish between a solipsistic universe (where its only your mind) and the universe of the actual world that we live in. This is because as I said earlier that all we truly know is our minds and its contents (it’s knowledge) and how other things beyond it cannot be known for absolute certainty. This makes the mind being an entity a priori it does not prove solipsism or show property dualism to be logically impossible only that in our world because of a priori truths that we have about our minds that property dualism is not true at least in our universe. Again the mind being an entity doesn’t say anything about its ontology as the entity itself can at least in principle have a material ontology in the case of materialism but it cannot simply reduce to properties or processes. There is of course an epistemic way one can show that the entity has a mental ontology but that only has to do with epistemology and not ontology.

3.EM: P4 is ridiculous there is clearly a difference between a solipsistic mind and a mind of the actual world. A solipsistic mind would be in which only the self exist while the mind in the actual world could be a mind where there is an external world outside the self
Response: I think it’s true that ontologically there is a difference between a solipsistic mind and the mind of the actual world (because I am NOT a solipsist) however this was not the point that P4 was trying to get at. It makes an epistemic claim about how epistemically we cannot know if our mind is the only thing that exist or not and of course epistemic claims are claims about ontological things.
Like the claim “If materialism is true then all that exist is material” can be divided into two claims when it comes to the epistemic/ontological distinction. The first “If materialism is true” is itself a matter of epistemology and the second “then all that exist is material” is a matter of ontology. This indicates that epistemology makes claims about ontological things. It’s not that epistemology has its own ontology but rather it can make claims about things that are ontological. This is important since in the case of our minds we can know a priori that it exist and that in the absence of anything else it would in fact be the only mind that exist. Now yes this only assumes that other things don’t exist but we can at least know from that epistemic starting point that the ontology in that starting point is mental. So clearly a priori we can know epistemically that there is no difference between a solipsistic mind and the one of the actual world. Then of course like I said before epistemology makes claims about ontological things.
This is the end of my response to EM. I think he misunderstood some of the main concepts in my original blog and I hope this response will help to clarify some of the issues. So in conclusion he has not been successful in refuting my criticisms of property dualism and I hope that we both can move on and learn more about philosophy of mind.
Endnotes

  1. “Why property dualism is absurd – Christian Idealism and apologetics.” 16 Aug. 2017, https://christianidealism.wordpress.com/2017/08/16/why-property-dualism-is-absurd/. Accessed 6 Sep. 2018.
  2. “The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Philosophy ….” https://www.amazon.com/Conscious-Mind-Search-Fundamental-Philosophy/dp/0195117891. Accessed 6 Sep. 2018.
  3. “The Character of Consciousness (Philosophy of Mind): David J ….” https://www.amazon.com/Character-Consciousness-Philosophy-Mind/dp/0195311116. Accessed 6 Sep. 2018.
  4. “Naïve realism – Wikipedia.” https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Na%C3%AFve_realism. Accessed 6 Sep. 2018.
  5. “Quantum erasure with causally disconnected choice.” 28 Jun. 2012, https://arxiv.org/abs/1206.6578. Accessed 6 Sep. 2018.